martes, 22 de mayo de 2012

The Role of Judges in Political Struggles

By Federico G. Thea*

Abstract.
The study of judicial behaviour has become increasingly important in the last decades, especially due to the increasing judicialization of the most fundamental political dilemmas in modern democracies. However, some traditional legalistic conceptions still assert that knowledge of judicial decision-making is exclusively linked to the study of positive law, and consider judges “as a unique body of impervious legal technicians above and beyond the political struggle”. In this essay, the importance of studies on judicial behaviour will be highlighted, and it will be argued that the traditional assertion that judges are ‘above and beyond’ the political struggle is fundamentally flawed. In so arguing, special attention will be paid, firstly, to the main approaches to empirical judicial studies. Secondly, a brief account of how the nature and structure of the various dissimilar judicial systems affect the political significance of courts and judicial decisions in different legal systems will be provided. Lastly, three cases concerning judicial intervention in core political quandaries in different jurisdictions will be examined (Bush v Gore, the Binyam Mohamed case, and the Berlusconi case); in order to analyse whether in deciding such prominent political dilemmas the judges positioned themselves ‘above and beyond’, ‘below and within’, or at some point in the middle of, the political struggle.



I.              Introduction.
Over the last few decades, many modern democracies have experienced an increasing judicialization of the most fundamental political dilemmas.[1] Thus, the study of judicial behaviour has become increasingly important, not only to gain more accurate knowledge of how judges make decisions, but also to improve judicial appointments[2] and accountability mechanisms.[3] Yet, neither legal theories nor social science’s empirical approaches have been able to provide a complete and coherent account of the key factors influencing judicial decisions.
On the one hand, traditional legal scholarship asserts that knowledge of judicial decision-making is exclusively linked to the study of positive law.[4] In Shapiro’s words, this legalistic approach considers judges “as a unique body of impervious legal technicians above and beyond the political struggle”.[5] On the other hand, “the view that…judges are policymakers has become all but axiomatic among political scientists”.[6] Although nowadays only a few legal scholars hold the traditional legalistic view,[7] the actual impact of politics in judicial decision-making is still subject to strong debate. Similarly, political scientists lack consensus on how judges’ political attitudes affect their decisions, as evinced, for instance, by the different approaches of the attitudinal, [8] the strategic[9] and the connectionist models,[10] amongst others.
In this essay, it will be argued that the traditional assertion that judges are ‘above and beyond’ the political struggle is fundamentally flawed. Furthermore, the great influence of politics in judicial decisions will be highlighted, while also recognising the relevance of many other factors. In so arguing, special attention will be paid, firstly, to the main approaches to empirical judicial studies. Although none of them is able to provide a complete account of how judges actually make decisions, they nevertheless constitute an extremely useful guideline to discover, understand and critically analyse the numerous factors that may influence the judicial decision-making process. For instance, they offer key information about the judges’ policy preferences, their background characteristics, institutional constraints, peer effects, their ‘managerial pressures’, or even the judges’ relationship with their audiences, amongst many others. Secondly, a brief account of how the nature and structure of the various dissimilar judicial systems affect the political significance of courts and judicial decisions in different legal systems will be provided, as a preface to the study of three of the most recent and relevant episodes of clash between judges and politicians worldwide. Lastly, these three cases concerning judicial intervention in core political quandaries in different jurisdictions will be examined, in order to study whether in deciding such prominent political dilemmas the judges positioned themselves ‘above and beyond’, ‘below and within’, or at some point in the middle of, the political struggle.
In summary, this essay will critically discuss the traditional assertion that judges limit themselves exclusively to applying the ‘positive law’, without being influenced by any ‘external factor’, in the light of the most recent and relevant empirical judicial studies; the comparative analysis of different judicial systems; and the study of three of the most important episodes of judicial intervention in core political questions worldwide. As a conclusion, it will be argued that judges are not at all “impervious legal technicians”, since there are many elements that affect the judicial decision-making process, including political factors as one of the most relevant.
II.           Mapping the judicial decision-making process.
Over the last several decades, a growing body of descriptive accounts of judging has tried to answer the difficult question of how judicial decisions are actually made (in contrast with legal theorists’ concern about how judges should make decisions), by recourse to a wide variety of empirical methods, which includes large-scale quantitative analysis of decisions,[11] attitude surveys (with and about judges), interviews with judges,[12] analysis of correspondence[13] and case simulations,[14] amongst others.
A pioneering empirical study, based on the quantitative analysis of judicial decisions, was conducted by Sheldon Goldman, between 1965 and 1971.[15] It was also one of the first works to examine in detail the impact of judges’ attitudes and personal background on their decisions. The research considered more than 2,000 non-unanimously decided cases of the United States Courts of Appeals, and labelled them into different categories, according to the topic of the decision.[16] In order to examine the impact of political attitudes in judicial behaviour, judges were scored a numerical value,[17] depending on whether their decisions on each topic had represented a politically liberal, intermediate or conservative attitude.[18] Thus, by comparing the judges’ score on each topic, the author examined whether or not there was a ‘politically determined’ trend in their decisions. In addition, the study also tested seven background variables, to determine their association with voting behaviour, namely: party affiliation, age, religion, prior judicial experience, years on appeals court, public prosecutorial acquaintance, and experience as a candidate before the electorate for public office.[19] Hence, by comparing the score of the different judges in each category, Goldman examined whether or not their voting behaviour on one topic was associated with others, so that an attitudinal or background pattern could be inferred. The results were extremely instructive. On balance, party affiliation, age and religion appeared as the most relevant background variables. At the aggregate level, though, none of these factors was found to have an actual significant effect on judicial behaviour. Conversely, “voting patterns…suggested the existence of interrelated political attitudes held by judges”,[20] which according to the author, allowed the interpretation of appeals court judges’ decisions as “representing gradations of broadly defined political and economic liberal-conservative attitudes”.[21] In summary, Goldman concluded that “attitudes and values defined politically rather than legally may be of prime importance in understanding appeals court voting behaviour”.[22] Notwithstanding the valuable contribution of this empirical study, it is necessary to avoid both the overestimation, as well as the undue generalisation, of its conclusions. In this regard, it has been argued that the empirical evidence is quite limited, since it does not conclusively establish that judges are motivated solely (or even overwhelmingly) by policy goals, but only shows that differences in judges’ position in the same cases may be better understood as a product of different policy preferences.[23] According to some commentators, the attitudinal model appears a very straightforward and simple version of rational choice theory “because it assumes that judges can maximize their utility simply by rendering whatever decision most pleases them ideologically, without regard to other institutions or considerations”.[24] Finally, as regards the research described above, it could also be argued that the conclusions inferred from Goldman’s empirical evidence cannot be generalised and used to analyse all judicial decision-making processes, since it was strictly circumscribed to study the judicial behaviour of appellate court judges, and exclusively in the United States. Despite these limitations, it would also be mistaken to overlook the importance of Goldman’s study. Firstly, because even when it does not provide a definite explanation of how judges actually make decisions, it nevertheless clearly demonstrates that traditional legalistic views, which categorically deny any influence of political or ideological attitudes in the judicial decision-making process are fundamentally flawed. And secondly, because not only did his study provide relevant evidence of the influence of judges’ beliefs and political attitudes in their decisions, but it also led the way to further researches on the impact of political attitudes in judicial decision-making, as well as to consider other possible variables, such as the judges’ personal background, and to develop alternative theoretical frameworks.
A prominent example of this evolution of empirical judicial studies is the contextual approach adopted by Cameron and Cummings, in their research on ‘Diversity and Judicial Decision-Making’.[25] Adopting a social economy approach, the authors focused on the peer effects in collegial courts. Thus, they distinguished between the impact of judges’ personal background on their own decisions (i.e. the ‘personal background effect’) and its impact on others (i.e. the ‘diversity effect’) from the peer effect, which is “the separate impact of other judges’ actions on [one] judge”.[26] In other words, the authors tested whether the interaction between judges with different political attitudes and personal backgrounds, sitting in the same panel, affected their deliberations and the collegiate decision-making process.[27] The study examined more than 500 votes cast on almost 200 three-judge panels on the U.S. Courts of Appeal, covering all affirmative action decisions from 1971 to 1999.[28] Amongst the main findings, Cameron and Cummings suggested that racial diversity had a strong peer effect on affirmative action voting.[29] According to the authors, “adding a single non-white member to a panel…increased the probability of pro-affirmative action voting of white judges by about fifteen percentage points”.[30] The few available data of gender diversity also showed “a weak relationship…between adding a female judge to a panel and the pro-affirmative action voting of the male judges”.[31] In these cases, they found “a direct ‘deliberation effect’ distinct from a peer pressure effect, which magnifies the influence through feedback into the other judges’ votes”.[32] However, the research also suggested that ideological diversity did not increase deliberation. Although it operated through peer effect, it did not guarantee a higher degree of deliberation.[33]  It had an ‘adverse’ peer effect, i.e. it polarised even more the divergent opinions.[34] Instead of adding deliberation, ‘ideological diversity’ in panel of judges seemed to increase polarisation about their political attitudes.[35] In any case, although ideological diversity did not appear to increase deliberation, it nevertheless had an impact on judges’ decisions that is important to consider when studying judicial decision-making. Finally, Cameron and Cummings stressed in their conclusions the benefits of racial and gender diversity in broadening the judges’ views and promoting deliberation in collegial courts.[36] Along the same line, Sir Terence Etherton has recently argued that “[t]he analysis of social psychologists, and the examples of their empirical research…highlight the importance on panels of appellate judges who, due to their diverse experience, can bring to bear on a case, particularly a hard case, a wider range of personal experience and judicial philosophies than would otherwise be the case. They will thereby make it more likely that the decision, and the reasoning which underpins it, will reflect the evolving values and institutions of the community, and that relevant arguments are not overlooked or brushed aside, and that insupportable preconceptions are challenged”.[37] However, it is important to note that the argument for judicial diversity is not necessarily dependent on demonstrating a contribution to the quality of justice since it is not dependent on outcomes, but there are strong arguments of equity and legitimacy to support it.[38] A usual question that arises when analysing this kind of empirical studies is whether or not their conclusions can be extended to other jurisdictions. In this regard, it is important to note, following Thomas, that the fact that this study was conducted in only one jurisdiction should not prevent the recognition of its relevance, in particular when developing the selection criteria for judicial appointment processes.[39] Nevertheless, it could also be argued that this research is limited to providing some useful, but partial, information of judicial decision-making. While the model followed by Cameron and Cummings shows why it would be mistaken to deny any ‘extra-legal’ influence on judges’ decisions, it also lacks a full explanation of how and why judges make decisions.
Attempting to overcome these limitations, some authors have provided a more complete and sophisticated account of judicial behaviour, based on the strategies designed by judges to master legal and institutional constraints in order to further their policy preferences in the long-term. One good example of this approach is the study conducted by Epstein and Knight, in The Choices Justices Make.[40] The authors examined correspondence between U.S. Supreme Court justices, during the 1970s and 1980s, focusing on the bargaining statements and the various changes of position that occurred throughout the process of deciding landmark cases.[41] For instance, when examining the decision-making process of Craig v. Boren, the authors found that the institutional rules of the Supreme Court had a strong impact on some justices’ switch of position after the conference that followed the oral hearing of the case, which could be better explained by their ‘strategic’ approach. For example, Justice Brennan, who was in charge of writing the opinion of the Court, initially favoured a ‘strict standard’ to analyse cases of laws discriminating on the basis of sex. However, he designed a ‘midlevel scrutiny test’ in order to get his colleagues support to arrive to a majority opinion. Although this ‘intermediate decision’ was not Brennan’s favourite option in terms of his ‘political attitudes’, it was more suitable to change the existing precedent that established a ‘rational basis test’, under which it would have been very hard to strike down laws containing sex-based classifications. Hence, the authors considered that Justice Brennan’s behaviour could be better understood by drawing more attention to the ‘strategy’ he designed to change the existing precedent rather than to his ‘political attitude’ regarding the topic. Similarly, they explained the changes of other Justices’ opinion based on the strategies they designed to pursue their objectives, rather than by looking at their ‘pure’ political attitudes.[42] Although it might be objected that this particular case examined by the authors is an isolated episode, their research also provides empirical evidence that justices’ strategic behaviour à la Craig is not anomalous. Interestingly, Epstein and Knight found that “[i]n more than half of all orally argued cases, the justices switch their votes, make changes in their opinions to accommodate the suggestions of colleagues, and join writings that do not necessarily reflect their sincere preferences”.[43] According to the authors, those cases evince the strategic behaviour of the judges, who “realize that their ability to achieve their goals depends on a consideration of the preferences of other actors, the choices they expect others to make, and the institutional context in which they act”.[44] For this reason, they contend that the attitudinal model fails to provide a complete account of judicial behaviour, since it overlooks the fact that while judges “may be motivated primarily by their policy preferences…they plainly are constrained in their attempts to implement those preferences”.[45] However, it should be noted that the strategic approach is also based on the controversial assumption that judges are motivated primarily by a desire to influence public policy.[46] Moreover, neither the attitudinal nor the strategic model accounts for the different type of judges (eg Supreme Court justices, appellate court judges or criminal court judges), who may have very diverse goals,[47] and whose decisions may have quite a dissimilar impact on policymaking. As noted by Baum, the strategic model also fails to consider the strong difficulties in the task of predicting the long-term consequences of judicial decisions, as well as in taking into account other simpler goals that judges may legitimately have, such as gaining the approval of their audiences,[48] or reducing caseload pressures.[49] Finally, it could also be argued that since ordinarily judges do not gain much benefit from advancing their favoured policies, and their individual decisions may not have any substantial impact on the totality of the policy, it would be quite unrealistic to analyse judges as purely strategic actors.[50] Notwithstanding these observations, the strategic model throws important light on many aspects of judicial behaviour that are not usually explored by traditional legal theories, or even by other empirical judicial studies. Moreover, it provides further evidence that political factors usually have an important, though not exclusive, influence in judicial decisions.
Another excellent example of the ‘post-attitudinal turn’ in judicial studies[51] is the study offered by Feeley and Rubin. In Judicial Policy-Making and the Modern State,[52] the authors centred their analysis in the American ‘Prison Reform Cases’, in order to show how “[p]olicy making may be contrasted with interpretation, which is the process by which public officials exercise power on the basis of a preexisting legal source that they regard as authoritative”.[53] This litigation saga, which took place in the United States between 1965 and 1990, is one of the most important examples of judicial policymaking. In fact, the judicial orders mandating prison reforms in different states of the Union were extremely comprehensive, and in some states the entire correctional system was designed following judicial orders.[54] Although Feeley and Rubin recognise that not all judicial decisions engage policymaking (and that the Prison Reform cases represent quite an extreme example in that regard) they claim that when judges do so “they invoke the text to establish their control over the subject matter, and then rely on nonauthoritative sources, and their own judgement, to generate a decision that is predominantly guided by the perceived desirability of its results”.[55] However, they argue that not only do traditional legal scholars fail to acknowledge this contrast but also, and more importantly, “judges continue to describe their policy-making role as an aspect of interpretation”.[56] According to the authors, while legal and institutional constraints do not prevent judicial policymaking, they may nevertheless create serious problems of legitimacy for the judiciary. For instance, they argue that in the ‘Prison Reform Cases’, the federal courts’ policymaking was contrary to the legal principles of separation of powers, federalism and the rule of law.[57] It is important to note that by arguing so, Feeley and Rubin do not criticise the decisions of the federal courts. Conversely, they stress the need to recognise that judicial policymaking is as necessary and legitimate as the other branches’, and therefore it should be studied accordingly.[58]
As already noted, the leading models of judicial behaviour provide important empirical evidence against the traditional assertion that judges are not influenced by any ‘extra-legal’ factor. Nevertheless, they have been subject to severe criticism due to their narrow perspective to analyse judicial behaviour. For example, Baum argues that the dominant models exaggerate the assumption that judges’ primary goals are grounded in their political attitudes, and he suggests that they “lack of a persuasive theory of judges’ motivations”.[59] Hence, he proposes to expand the scope of judicial studies and provide alternative approaches.[60] In this vein, his study on Judges and their audiences aims at demonstrating that judges’ interest in approval from their audiences (which may include not only their colleagues, but also the general public, other branches of government, legal policy groups, the media, etc.) has a great explanatory value to understand how judges actually make decisions.[61] Although this approach does not appear as the most attractive explanation of the judicial decision-making process, it is important to recall that it does not intend to provide a full account of judicial behaviour, but only to offer an additional alternative approach in order to broaden the analytical perspective. This view presupposes, then, that the different approaches to judicial studies should not be regarded as competing or mutually exclusive models, but as complementary perspectives, which partially capture certain features of the extremely complex judicial decision-making process.
Similarly, the more recent connectionist models recognise that a sophisticated understanding of judicial decision making “require[s] the integration of a range of disparate, and potentially inconsistent, information and objectives”.[62] In this regard, Robbennolt et al stress the importance of taking into consideration that different judges may have very diverse goals. For instance, they argue that while trial court judges are likely to focus on issues of caseload management, or pre-trial settlement; appellate judges may engage in more ‘policymaking’ quandaries; and elected judges are probably more influenced by political concerns regarding their re-election.[63] Moreover, it could be added that there are important differences in the judges’ goals depending on the structure of their respective judicial systems; [64] the jurisdictional fragmentation;[65] or on whether they are municipal judges or they sit in international courts; amongst many other possible classifications. However, Robbennolt et al also argue that even one single judge may face many different, and sometimes contradictory, objectives. In order to illustrate their argument, the authors give as example the many conflicting goals that a criminal judge may have to consider before deciding a motion to suppress key evidence in a difficult (but not uncommon) criminal trial,[66] and analyse this imaginary case using the theoretical tools provided by the connectionist model of constraint satisfaction.  As a result, they conclude that this model may provide a better explanation of the extremely complex judicial decision-making process than researches focused on only one main factor, because it offers “a set of ‘goal management principles’ that can describe the interrelations among the disparate goals and actions pursued by legal decision makers”.[67] In particular, it examines the extent to which specific goals can be satisfied by available choices (‘principle of equifinality’), how some actions are likely to fulfil goals better than others (‘principle of best fit’) or fulfil numerous goals at once (‘principle of multifinality’), and how some goals may inevitably conflict without allowing their concurrent achievement (‘principle of goal incompatibility’).[68] According to the authors, this model overcomes the simplicity of other approaches, and provides a more accurate and realistic analysis of the judicial decision-making process. Nevertheless, even when it offers a wider perspective of judicial behaviour, it could be argued that it fails to explain how judges actually balance all these factors when making a decision. In any case, it should also be recognised that this alternative model provides important further evidence that judges do not pursue a single objective when making decisions, and that there are many ‘extra-legal’ factors that affect the judicial decision-making process.
All things considered then, it would be fair to conclude that although the most influential empirical judicial studies are not still able to offer a definite and complete explanation of how judges actually make decisions, they nevertheless provide clear evidence that judges are far from being “impervious legal technicians”. These studies clearly show how the numerous factors that influence judicial behaviour prevent any attempt to place the judiciary “above and beyond the political struggle”. However, a final qualification needs to be made. It is important to note that most of the empirical studies described above have been conducted in the United States. Therefore, before proceeding with the next section’s case-studies on clashes between judges and politicians in different jurisdictions, it seems appropriate to briefly explore how the nature and structure of dissimilar judicial systems and the role of judges in different legal systems may also influence the political significance of courts and judicial decisions.
Firstly, it is critical to distinguish whether the courts’ jurisdiction is concentrated (i.e. unitary systems, such as the judicial system of England and Wales) or separated into different hierarchical structures (i.e. fragmented systems, such as the Italian judicial system), which includes ‘special courts’ (eg administrative courts or/and constitutional courts, separated from the ‘ordinary’ civil and criminal courts). As explained by Guarnieri and Pederzoli, “the more far-reaching the scope of judicial decisions is the more politically significant a judge’s role is likely to be”.[69] Therefore, “[t]he fragmentation of the judicial system can…be seen as a means of politically neutralizing ordinary courts while preserving their institutional independence”.[70] Secondly, the internal dynamics, i.e. the interaction between the various actors of the ‘judicial pyramid’, also affects the significance and powers of courts in the different judicial systems. According to Guarnieri and Pederzoli, the ‘hierarchical system’, usually adopted in countries with bureaucratic judiciaries (eg Italy, Spain, France) enables appellate and supreme courts to exercise a higher degree of control over the lower courts than the ‘co-ordinate system’, which is normally related to professional judiciaries (eg United States, and England and Wales).[71] In the authors’ opinion, although systems with a ‘hierarchical model’ may provide more coherence amongst the different judges’ decisions, they also reduce the political significance of ordinary courts, which in ‘co-ordinate’ systems is usually higher.[72] Another important factor to consider when studying the influence of politics in different judicial systems is the openness of courts to individual and group litigants, and their perception about the relative utility of courts.[73] In this regard, Guarnieri and Pederzoli argue, on the one hand, that “[t]he lower the threshold of access, especially for interest groups, the stronger is the relative [political] importance of courts”.[74] On the other hand, they also suggest that the existence of quasi-judicial institutions which can effectively process conflicts may foster court avoidance and thus ‘dejudicialization’ in some policy areas”.[75] In relation to the citizens’ perception of the judiciary’s usefulness as “a channel for the articulation of political demands”, it is also important to take into account the different judicial prerogatives as regards the review of legislation. For instance, it could be argued that systems allowing diffuse review of legislation confer more power (and, consequently, more ‘political relevance’) to ordinary courts than centralised systems, where constitutionality issues are entrusted to a single separate court. Similarly, the differences between concrete and abstract review of legislation, and the determination of the actors allowed to trigger this review (i.e. whether there is a direct or indirect appeal to judicial review of legislation), may also affect the relationship between judges and politicians in different jurisdictions.[76] Finally, it is important to consider how the different role assigned to other key actors of the judicial system, such as lawyers and public prosecutors, may also affect the political significance of courts and judicial decisions.[77] Firstly, as regard the latter, the civil and common law worlds present important differences, not only on the prosecutors’ powers, but also concerning their relationship with the judges, the police and the executive branch of government.[78] As explained by Guarnieri and Pederzoli, “the more autonomy prosecutors enjoy from other political institutions the greater the political significance of the judicial system”.[79] In this regard, the Berlusconi case, analysed below, will provide an excellent example of how the independent status of prosecutors in Italy increased their political significance. Secondly, the role of lawyers in the judicial systems also varies from inquisitorial to adversarial systems, where parties to the dispute may have more influence in the judicial decision, not only in criminal law cases but also as regards civil litigation.[80] The Binyam case, which will also be analysed below, provides a clear illustration of how litigant lawyers in an adversarial system (in that case, England and Wales) may affect the judicial decision-making process, even in ‘politically sensible’ cases.
III.        Judicialization of politics and politicisation of the judiciary.
The judicial studies accounted above not only provide empirical evidence of the range of factors influencing judicial decisions, but they also show that “[t]he interrelationship between judicial systems, law, and politics is dynamic and constantly changing”.[81] As noted by Domingo, “[t]he degree to which courts take part in policy or law making, or the extent to which political and social disputes can be resolved through legal recourse, varies greatly from country to country, and also over time”. [82] Therefore, it seems appropriate to analyse recent cases concerning judicial intervention in core political quandaries from different judicial systems, in order to put the study of the judges’ role in political struggles in context.
An extremely useful and rich case study to begin with is the U.S. Supreme Court’s decision in Bush v. Gore, which not only generated significant debate as to the impact of the judges’ political attitudes in the final judgement, but also with regard to their partisan affiliation.[83] The case arose due to the possible miscalculation in the counting of votes in Florida, whose final result would determine the outcome of the U.S. presidential election of 2000. Since the margin of victory of the republican candidate, George W. Bush, over the democrat one, Al Gore, was minimal (only 327 votes), the Florida Supreme Court agreed and ordered a recount of the so called ‘undervotes’, i.e. the ballots in which machine counts had not detected any choice for President.[84] However, the following day (December 9), the U.S. Supreme Court issued a stay of the Florida Court’s ruling, arguing that “[t]he counting of votes…threaten[s] irreparable harm to petitioner [George Bush], and to the country, by casting a cloud upon what he claims to be the legitimacy of his election.”[85] Finally, on December 12, the Court issued the final decision, reversing the Supreme Court of Florida’s judgment of December 8, on the grounds that the recount it had ordered violated the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment.[86]
From a traditional legalistic point of view, some commentators argued that the Court limited itself to applying the law, without being influenced by other factors. [87] However, the weakness of the legal arguments used by the judges does not support this thesis. Moreover, as suggested by Dworkin, it is “difficult to find a respectable explanation of why all and only the conservatives voted to end the election in this way”.[88] In sharp contrast to the traditional legalistic views, other theories, such as legal realism and the critical legal studies, as well as many approaches from the social sciences, would argue that political attitudes played a key role in the decision-making, shaping the way judges interpreted the law. However, as pointed out both by Dworkin and Balkin, the conservative judges’ decision did not reflect their political opinion regarding issues of federalism, judicial activism, the extension of the equal protection clause, or any other constitutional question, but quite the opposite. Consequently, these authors discard the hypothesis of the ideological attitudes’ effect on the decision, and suggest instead that “this is a more overt collapse of the boundary between law and politics…”[89] A final alternative analysis, following a pragmatist approach, would explain Bush v. Gore considering the possible consequences of the decision for the future of the country, arguing that the Court might have chosen values such as security and legal certainty over justice. [90] However, it is certainly hard to see a plausible alternative to the crude partisan explanation of the case, which positions the Court ‘below and within’, rather than ‘above and beyond’, the political struggle. Still, as it flows from the myriad of views described above, there are many factors that could have influenced the justices’ decision in Bush v. Gore, and therefore, neither a pure legalistic nor a ‘crude partisan’ approach seems to provide a complete explanation of the case.
At this point, it is important to highlight that the clash between judges and politicians is a worldwide phenomenon that affects not only states with checks and balances systems, such as the U.S., but also states enjoying a higher degree of political centralisation, such as the U.K., where the constitutional system is grounded on the doctrine of Parliamentary sovereignty.[91] In fact, the U.K. has recently provided a good example of high profile conflict between judges and politicians, in the ‘Binyam Mohamed affair’. The case arose from the detention by U.S. authorities of Binyam Mohamed (BM), an Ethiopian national who was seeking political asylum in the U.K. since 1994, and had been given temporary leave to remain as a U.K. resident. In 2001, BM travelled to Afghanistan, and then moved to Pakistan, where he was arrested in April 2002, and finally sent to Guantanamo Bay two years later, where he was charged with terrorist offences.
The British stage of this affair began in 2007, when BM sought disclosure of classified documents from the U.K.’s Government, which might support his defence that confessions obtained under torture by the U.S. Government were inadmissible as evidence against him. Since the British Foreign Secretary refused to disclose such information, BM applied for judicial review, relying on the ‘Norwich Pharmacal principle’,[92] according to which a third party who has been involved in allegedly unlawful action by somebody else should disclose relevant information in his possession to the victim. In its first open judgement, the Divisional Court held that the U.K.’s Security Service and Secret Intelligence Service had facilitated arguable wrongdoing and therefore, an order for disclosure under the ‘Norwich Pharmacal principle’ would be made, albeit subject to any public interest immunity claim by the Foreign Secretary.[93] The information sought by BM was subsequently made available in the habeas corpus proceedings opened in the U.S., leading to his release from Guantanamo and later return to the U.K. in 2009.[94] However, an incidental issue concerning the final drafting of the written judgement remained open, and would generate an unprecedented clash between judges and politicians.
The seed of the conflict was the Foreign Secretary’s opposition to the restoration of seven paragraphs that had been redacted from the first open judgment in Binyam, which summarised U.S. reports concerning BM’s treatment by U.S. officials, in the knowledge of which the U.K. had continued to supply information for use in the interrogations. The paragraphs said, inter alia, that “the treatment reported…could readily be contended to be at the very least cruel, inhuman and degrading treatment of BM by the United States authorities”.[95] The Foreign Secretary’s arguments were set out in three public interest immunity certificates, which asserted that the publication of the redacted paragraphs would violate the general control principle over intelligence arrangements and, moreover, that in the event of disclosure the U.S. would re-evaluate its intelligence ‘special’ sharing relationship with the U.K., which would seriously prejudice the national security. Since during the Bush administration there was strong evidence supporting these arguments, the Divisional Court held in its fourth open judgment that the redacted paragraphs would not be restored. However, Obama’s assumption of the U.S. presidential office in January 2009 would radically change the situation. In fact, evidence produced before the Court made clear that President Obama had expressed very different views on torture, interrogation techniques and transparency from those of the Bush administration’s officials. Consequently, the Divisional Court held in its fifth open judgement, in October 2009, that the public interest in the disclosure of the paragraphs outweighed the national security risk involved in the case. [96] However, the Foreign Secretary raised further security concerns against the draft of this judgment, which were dismissed by the Court,[97] though the redacted paragraphs would not be published yet due to the Government’s appeal.
At the appellate stage, Jonathan Sumption QC, representing the Foreign Secretary, vehemently attacked the Divisional Court’s judges, affirming that their attitude had been irresponsible, unnecessary and “profoundly damaging to the interests of this country”.[98] Although the Court of Appeal affirmed that the Divisional Court had given insufficient weight to the PII certificates, it nevertheless dismissed the appeal. [99] However, the conflict was not over, and it would have a further twist. After distributing its draft judgment to the parties, the Court of Appeal received some suggestions by Sumption QC, and made further changes on a paragraph containing strong criticism of the U.K.’s Security Service. However, counsel for BM (Dinah Rose QC) had not received the letter in time to register objections. When Dinah Rose got Sumption’s letter (one day before the second draft judgment would be made public) she handed it to the press, leaking therefore many details of the conflict,[100] including the controversial paragraph [168], which read, inter alia, that “…some security services officials appear to have a dubious record relating to actual involvement, and frankness about any such involvement, with the mistreatment of Mr. Mohamed…”[101] Finally, on February 26, the Court of Appeal wrote a third version of the contested paragraph, restoring some criticisms but explaining their limits. More importantly, it waived the confidentiality understanding on which the first draft judgment had been circulated “in order to dispel the damaging myth or lingering public perception that a minister or his counsel had been permitted to interfere with the judicial process”.[102]
Although there was some ‘bad taste’ surrounding this conflict, [103] the Court of Appeal tried to overcome the controversially political tone of the case with a remarkable final judgment that honoured the principle of open justice and judicial independence. However, it is difficult to see how the judges intervening in the case could have positioned themselves “above and beyond the political struggle”, since the whole satellite litigation in Binyam as to the drafting, redacting, re-drafting and publication of the controversial paragraphs inherently contained more political than strictly legal features. Furthermore, not only did the ‘Binyam affair’ concern a clash between judges and politicians, but also arguably the judicial appointment process. In fact, only a few weeks after the final judgment, a new member of the U.K. Supreme Court was announced (Lord Dyson), [104] after one of the allegedly main candidates had suddenly withdrawn his application in December 2009. Interestingly, the retired candidate was Sumption QC, who from being the favourite for the post became a reject, due to the opposition from some judges of both the Court of Appeal and the Supreme Court.[105] His appointment to the Supreme Court would have to wait until this year, when due to the retirement of Lord Saville and the imminent departure of Lord Collins, it was announced that Lord Justice Wilson and Jonathan Sumption QC would fill those vacancies.[106] From the above analysis, it is clear that many ‘non legal’ factors could have influenced the different decisions in Binyam, which positioned judges closer to the middle of, rather than above and beyond, the ‘political struggle’.
A final illustration of a judicialized conflict with blurred boundaries between law and politics is the ‘Berlusconi case’ in Italy, where unlike the U.K., there is a long history of clashes and collusions between judges[107] and politicians. The tension, however, would not reach its peak until the early 1990s, when the extremely high profile of the Mani pulite (clean hands) investigations of corruption produced what has been termed a ‘revolution by the judges’, which led to the collapse of the hitherto dominant Christian Democracy party and its allies, and the beginning of the Second Republic.[108] In this context, the judiciary gained great popularity among the public,[109] and the degree of ‘politicisation’ of judges was so unusually high that even some of them resigned from the judiciary and started a political career.[110] In turn, some politicians reacted against the increasing judicial activism in the political arena, and attempted to de-legitimise the judiciary,[111] by denouncing conspiracies[112] and generating constant confrontations. Unsurprisingly, Silvio Berlusconi played a ‘leading role’ in these attacks.
In this historical context, the so-called ‘Berlusconi Case’ arose, as an extreme example of a long-term conflict between the judiciary and the political power in Italy. The case concerns a legal (and political) battle to pass immunity laws to the highest political offices, which were allegedly orientated to override the judicial investigations opened against Berlusconi for corruption[113] and, more recently, for juvenile prostitution and abuse of power.[114] This conflict began in 2003, after the passing of Law Nº 140 (‘lodo Schifani’),[115] which provided for an automatic, general and not-limited-in-time suspension of any criminal proceedings against the highest political offices in Italy. The Italian Constitutional Court declared this law partially unconstitutional in 2004.[116] However, the political majority insisted with a new immunity law in 2008 (‘lodo Alfano’),[117] which was widely criticized as a copy of the previous one. Thus, in October 2009 the Italian Constitutional annulled the law once again.[118] Nevertheless, not only did Berlusconi repeat his furious attack against the judiciary, but he also promoted a new law to stop judicial investigations on him. The third attempt was made through the ‘legitimate impediment law’, passed in 2010, which provided a suspension of court proceedings for up to 18 months in the case of members of the government. However, in a new episode of the conflict, the Constitutional Court declared this law partially unconstitutional, stating that Berlusconi could not automatically invoke a “legitimate impediment” claim exempting him and cabinet ministers from attending trials in progress because of their official duties.[119]
The ‘Berlusconi case’ is an extreme example of blurred boundaries between law and politics, which confirms that judges can hardly position themselves ‘above and beyond the political struggle’. However, it also demonstrates that even in the most ‘politicised’ conflicts, political attitudes are not an exclusive factor affecting judicial decisions. For instance, it could be argued that the legal arguments based on the Italian Constitution were key factors in the decisions of the Constitutional Court. In fact, as distinct from Bush v. Gore, Italian scholars and commentators almost unanimously agreed with the Constitutional Court that the contested immunity laws were contrary to the Italian Constitution.[120] Hence, neither political attitudes nor legal arguments were the exclusive reasons behind this case, but only some amongst many others.
IV.         Conclusion.
There is great uncertainly when trying to explain how and why judges make decisions. Nevertheless, judicial studies provide enormous help to overcome the traditional dogmatic and simplistic views of judicial behaviour, which prevent more realistic and accurate explanations. As described in the introduction, there are still some traditional legal approaches claiming that it is possible to predict any judicial decision, by simply applying analogical reasoning to the legal precedents and statutes; and denying the effect of any ‘non-legal’ factor in the judicial decision-making process. Therefore, even when the empirical judicial studies analysed in this essay did not provide a complete and definite answer about the factors that affect judicial behaviour, they nevertheless taught important lesson on the complexity of the process, which evinced the unsuitability of the traditional legalistic models. The first conclusion of this essay is, then, that simplistic explanations of judicial behaviour will never be able to provide a successful account of the judicial decision-making process.
The main argument of this essay was that the traditional characterisation of judges as “a unique body of impervious legal technicians above and beyond the political struggle” was fundamentally flawed. In arguing so, a critical account of the most recent and relevant empirical models of judicial behaviour was given, in order to show the myriad of factors that may influence judicial decisions. As already noted, while none of these studies provides definite answers, each of them throws important light on some aspects of the extremely complex process of judicial decision-making, and more importantly, they clearly demonstrate that judges are affected by many ‘extra-legal’ factors. Hence, it is completely misguided to consider judges as “impervious legal technicians”. In addition, the comparative analysis of the nature and structure of different judicial systems aimed at showing that it is not possible to reach universal answers on this topic, since the factors affecting judicial behaviour also depend on the special characteristics of each jurisdiction.
Finally, the study of three cases concerning judicial intervention in core political quandaries in different jurisdictions aimed at demonstrating the increasing “judicialization of politics and politicisation of the judiciary”, a phenomenon that prevents any positioning of judges “above and beyond the political struggle”. Nevertheless, these cases also showed that neither political attitudes nor legal arguments were the exclusive reasons behind the respective judicial decisions, but only some amongst many others.
To conclude, judges in modern democracies are neither “a unique body of impervious legal technicians above and beyond the political struggle” nor a ‘political party’. Therefore, it would also be mistaken to overvalue the influence of politics in the judicial decision-making process. As the cases commented in the last section clearly show, there are many factors influencing judicial decisions, which allow multiple and varied interpretations. This lack of certainty regarding the actual factors affecting the judicial behaviour should not, however, lead to an underestimation of the relevance of the various empirical studies and legal theories on the subject, which provide extremely useful tools to analyse judicial decisions, and to better understand how judges actually make decisions.


[1] Ran Hirschl, ‘The Judicialization of Mega-Politics and the Rise of Political Courts’ (2008) 11 Annual Review of Political Science 1; See also, Cheryl Thomas (ed), The Power of Judges: A Comparative Study of Courts and Democracy, by Guarnieri, and Pederzoli (OUP 2002) 1; Robert Stevens, The English Judges: Their Role in the Changing Constitution (Hart Publishing 2002)
[2] Judith Resnik ‘Judicial Selection and Democratic Theory: Demand, Supply, and Life tenure’ (2005) 26 Cardozo Law Review 579; Cheryl Thomas, Judicial Diversity in the United Kingdom and Other Jurisdictions: A Review of Research, Policy and Practices (Commission for Judicial Appointments 2005); Brenda Hale, ‘The Appointment and Removal of Judges: Independence and Diversity’ (2006) Speech to the International Association of Women Judges, 8th biennial conference, 3–7 May, Sydney, Australia; Kate Malleson, ‘Creating a judicial appointments commission: which model works best?’ (2004) Public Law 102; Kate Malleson, ‘Rethinking the Merit Principle in Judicial Selection’ (2006) 33 Journal of Law and Society (1) 126.
[3] Daniela Piana, ‘Beyond Judicial Independence’ (2010) 9 Comparative Sociology 40, 52.
[4] Malcolm Feeley and Edward Rubin, Judicial Policy-Making and the Modern State (Cambridge UP 1999) 2.
[5] Marin Shapiro, Law and politics in the Supreme Court: new approaches to Political Jurisprudence (Free Press 1964) 21.
[6] Anne Bloom, ‘The "Post-Attitudinal Moment": Judicial Policymaking through the Lens of New Institutionalism’ (2001) 35 Laws & Society Review 1, 219.
[7] Lawrence Baum, Judges and Their Audiences (Princeton UP 2006) 8.
[8] Sheldon Goldman, ‘Voting Behavior on the United States Courts of Appeal Revisited’ (1975) 69 American Political Science Review 491.
[9] Lee Epstein and Jack Knight, The Choices Justices Make (Congressional Quarterly Press 1997).
[10] Jennifer Robbennolt, Robert MacCoun and John Darley, ‘Multiple Constraint Satisfaction in Judging’, in Klein and Mitchell (eds), The Psychology of Judicial Decision-Making (OUP 2010).
[11] Goldman (n 8); Charles Cameron and Craig Cummings, ‘Diversity and Judicial Decision-Making: Evidence from Affirmative Action Cases in the Federal Courts of Appeal 1971-1999’ (2003) Paper Presented at the 2003 Meeting of the Midwest Political Science Association.
[12] Jessica Jacobson and Mike Hough, Mitigation: The Role of Personal Factors in Sentencing (Prison Reform Trust 2007).
[13] Epstein and Knight (n 9); Feeley and Rubin (n 4).
[14] Austin Lovegrove, ‘Public Opinion, Sentencing and Lenience: An Empirical Study Involving Judges Consulting the Community’ (2007) Criminal Law Review 769.
[15] Goldman (n 8) 491.
[16] ibid 491-493.
[17] ibid 491.
[18] It is important to stress that, in order to label a judge as liberal, conservative or intermediate regarding one topic, at least five of his decisions on that particular issue had to be calculated and analysed.
[19] Goldman (n 8) 491.
[20] ibid 505.
[21] ibid.
[22] ibid 495.
[23] Baum (n 7) 20.
[24] Frank Cross, ‘Political Science and the new legal realism: a case of unfortunate interdisciplinary ignorance’ (1997) 92 Northwestern University Law Review 251, 265; Baum (n 7) 5.
[25] Cameron and Cummings (n 11).
[26] ibid 4.
[27] ibid 1.
[28] ibid 4.
[29] ibid 18.
[30] ibid 19.
[31] ibid.
[32] ibid 25.
[33] ibid 26.
[34] In this vein, a recent “experimental investigation involving two deliberative exercises, one among self-identified liberals and another among self-identified conservatives, showed that participants' views became more extreme after deliberation”. See David Schkade, Cass Sunstein and Reid Hastie, ‘When deliberation produces extremism’ (2010) 22 Critical Review (2) 227.
[35] Cameron and Cummings (n 11) 20.
[36] ibid 28.
[37] Terence Etherton, ‘Liberty, the archetype and diversity: a philosophy of judging’, (2010) Public Law 727, 746. See also Brenda Hale, ‘Equality and the Judiciary: Why Should We Want More Women Judges? (2001) Public Law 489.
[38] Kate Malleson, ‘Justifying gender equality on the bench: why difference won't do’ (2003) 11 Feminist Legal Studies 1. According to this author, “[o]ne can hope that a more diverse judiciary may include a wider range of skills and experience which will enhance the quality of its decision-making in a general sense. But the primary rationale for wishing to appoint judges from more diverse backgrounds is to strengthen the legitimacy of the judiciary. Irrespective of whether or not the inclusion on the bench of members of under-represented groups such as solicitors, women, minority lawyers and disabled lawyers will have a significant effect on the decision-making of the courts, the corrosive impact of their absence on the legitimacy of the judiciary is now too great to ignore”. See Malleson, ‘Creating a judicial appointments commission: which model works best?’ (n 2) 106. Along the same line, Etherton argues that the composition of the judiciary, and in particular its diversity, are important in securing and maintaining their legitimacy for two reasons. Firstly, because “the composition of the judiciary can then be seen to reflect the very values of which they are the guardians –human rights and equality inherent in a liberal democracy…And secondly, because a judiciary which is not reflective of the different elements within the community, particularly minority groups, is less likely to command their respect”. See, Etherton (n 37) 743-744.
[39] Cheryl Thomas, Judicial Diversity in the United Kingdom and Other Jurisdictions (n 2) 60. See also Kate Malleson, ‘Promoting Diversity in the Judiciary: Reforming the Judicial Appointments Process’, in Philip. Thomas (ed), Discriminating Lawyers (Cavendish Press 2000).
[40] Epstein and Knight (n 9).
[41] Bloom (n 6) 221.
[42] Epstein and Knight (n 9) 9.
[43] ibid.
[44] ibid 10.
[45] Bloom (n 6) 220.
[46] ibid 223.
[47] Robbennolt, MacCoun and Darley (n 10).
[48] Baum (n 7) 15-16.
[49] Robbennolt, MacCoun and Darley (n 10) 29.
[50] Baum (n 7) 15-16.
[51] i.e., the increasing trend to “look much further than judicial attitudes…[and] examine how institutional structures shape and constrain judicial policymaking” See Bloom (n 6) 220.
[52] Feeley and Rubin (n 4).
[53] ibid 5.
[54] Bloom (n 6) 224.
[55] ibid.
[56] ibid 11.
[57] ibid 18.
[58] ibid 22.
[59] Baum (n 7) 19.
[60] ibid 21.
[61] ibid 19.
[62] Robbennolt, MacCoun and Darley (n 10) 33.
[63] ibid 31-32.
[64] Cheryl Thomas (ed), The Power of Judges (n 1) 78.
[65] ibid 148.
[66] Robbennolt, MacCoun and Darley (n 10) 36.
[67] ibid 34-35.
[68] ibid 35.
[69] Cheryl Thomas (ed), The Power of Judges (n 1) 79.
[70] ibid.
[71] ibid 80-81.
[72] ibid.
[73] ibid 103-104.
[74] ibid 148.
[75] ibid 104.
[76] ibid 134-147.
[77] See Alan Paterson, Lawyers and the Public Good (The Hamlyn Lectures) (CUP, 2012)
[78] Cheryl Thomas (ed), The Power of Judges (n 1) 108-120.
[79] ibid 120.
[80] ibid 122.
[81] Pilar Domingo, ‘Judicialization of politics or politicization of the judiciary? Recent trends in Latin America’ (2004) 11 Democratization 104, 106.
[82] ibid.
[83] Ronald Dworkin, ‘A Badly Flawed Election’ The New York Review of Books (New York, 11 January 2001) 3; Jack Balkin, ‘Bush v. Gore and the Boundary Between Law and Politics’ (2001) 110 The Yale Law Journal 1407, 1408.
[84] Gore v. Harris, 772 So. 2d 1243 (Fla.2000).
[85] Bush v. Gore, 531 U.S. 98 (2000), Application for Stay (Scalia, J., concurring).
[86] Bush v. Gore, 531 U.S. 98 (2000), per curiam.
[87] Charles Fried, ‘A Badly Flawed Election: An Exchange’ The New York Review of Books (New York, 22 February 2001)
[88] Dworkin  (n 83) 2.
[89] ibid.
[90] Richard Posner, ‘Bush v. Gore as Pragmatic Adjudication’, in Ronald Dworkin (ed), A badly Flawed Election: Debating Bush v. Gore, the Supreme Court, and American Democracy (New Press 2002) 201; Agustin Gordillo, An Introduction to Law (Esperia Publications 2003), 138.
[91] Cheryl Thomas (ed), The Power of Judges (n 1) 155. See also Stevens (n 1)
[92] Norwich Pharmacal v Commissioners of Customs and Excise, [1974] AC 133.
[93] R (Binyam Mohamed) v Secretary of State for Foreign and Commonwealth Affairs [2008] EWHC 2048 (Admin).
[94] Richard Norton-Taylor, Peter Walker and Robert Booth, ‘Binyam Mohamed returns to Britain after Guantánamo ordeal’ The Guardian (London, 23 February 2009) <http://www.guardian.co.uk/ uk/2009/feb/23/binyam-mohamed-guantanamo-plane-lands> accessed 6 July 2011.
[95] R (Binyam Mohamed) v Secretary of State for Foreign and Commonwealth Affairs [2010] EWCA Civ 65, 32.
[96] R (Binyam Mohamed) v Secretary of State for Foreign and Commonwealth Affairs [2009] EWHC 2549 (Admin).
[97] ibid.
[98] John Aston and Cathy Gordon, ‘Minister's lawyers attack ‘torture’ case judges’ The Independent (London, 14 December 2009) <http://www.independent.co.uk/news/uk/home-news/ministers-lawyers-attack-torture-case-judges-1840649.html> accessed 6 July 2011; Richard Norton-Taylor, ‘Judges irresponsible for wanting CIA torture evidence disclosed, court told’ The Guardian (London, 14 December 2009) <http://www.guardian.co.uk/world/2009/dec/14/binyam-mohamed-cia-toture-appeal> accessed 6 July 2011.
[99] Binyam (n 95)
[100] Katy Dowell, ‘Dinah Rose QC apologises to court for handing Sumption letter to press’ The Lawyer (London, 11 February 2010) <http://www.thelawyer.com/1003432.article> accessed 6 July 2011.
[101] ibid.
[102] R (Binyam Mohamed) v Secretary of State for Foreign and Commonwealth Affairs [2010] EWCA Civ 158.
[103] Frances Gibb, ‘Analysis: victory for common sense and open justice’ The Sunday Times (London, 26 February 2010) <http://business.timesonline.co.uk/tol/business/law/article7042626.ece> accessed 6 July 2011.
[104] Margaret Taylor, ‘Dyson LJ named as final Supreme Court justice’ The Lawyer (London, 23 March 2010) <http://www.thelawyer.com/dyson-lj-named-as-final-supreme-court-justice/1003889.article> accessed 6 July 2011.
[105] Frances Gibb, ‘Supreme ambition, jealousy and outrage’ The Sunday Times (London, 4 February 2010) <http://business.timesonline.co.uk/tol/business/law/article7013960.ece> accessed 6 July 2011.
[106] However, Sumption QC has obtained permission to delay his ascent to the Supreme Court until after the Berezovsky v Abramovich case is heard, in order to fulfil his litigation work for Roman Abramovitch. See Owen Bowcott, ‘Supreme court judges appointed’ The Guardian (London, 4 May 2011) <http://www.guardian.co.uk/law/2011/may/04/supreme-court-judges-wilson-sumption> accessed 14 September 2011.
[107] In Italian, the term giudice (ie judge) includes investigating magistrates and judges of the bench as well as public prosecutors. Donatella Della Porta, ‘A judges’ revolution? Political corruption and the judiciary in Italy’ (2001) 39 European Journal of Political Research 1, 11.
[108] ibid 4.
[109] ibid 8; Cheryl Thomas (ed), The Power of Judges (n 1) 176.
[110] eg Antoinio Di Pietro and Luigi De Magistris.
[111] Della Porta (n 107) 11.
[112] ibid 10.
[113] John Hooper, ‘Silvio Berlusconi to face charges as early as next week, prosecutors say’ The Guardian (London, 2 February 2011) <http://www.guardian.co.uk/world/2011/feb/02/silvio-berlusconi-sex-prosecution> accessed 6 July 2011.
[114] John Hooper, ‘Silvio Berlusconi to face charges as early as next week, prosecutors say’ The Guardian (London, 2 February 2011) <http://www.guardian.co.uk/world/2011/feb/02/silvio-berlusconi-sex-prosecution> accessed 6 July 2011; John Hooper, ‘David Mills guilty of taking bribe linked to Berlusconi trials’ The Guardian (London, 17 February 2009) <http://www.guardian.co.uk/politics/2009/feb/17/david-mills-silvio-berlusconi-trial> accessed 6 July 2011.
[115]Lodo’ because it was a compromise reached by the political majority and the opposition; and ‘Schifani’, after its principal promoter, Renato Schifani, who at that time was President of the Italian Senate. See Giuseppe Martinico, ‘The Berlusconi Judgment: A Brief Case Note on the Decision of the Italian Constitutional Court (Note 262/2009)’ (2010) 16 European Public Law (2) 231.
[116] Italian Constitutional Court, Judgment 24/2004.
[117] In this case, it was named after Berlusconi's Minister of Justice Angelino Alfano. See Martinico (n 115)
[118] Italian Constitutional Court, Judgment 292/2009.
[119] John Hooper, ‘Italian court waters down Berlusconi immunity law’ The Guardian (London, 13 January 2011) <http://www.guardian.co.uk/world/2011/jan/13/italian-court-berlusconi-immunity-law> accessed 6 July 2011.
[120] Martinico (n 115).